Is War in Our Nature? What Is Right and What Is Wrong about the Seville Statement on Violence. Azar Gat. Human Nature, June 2019, Volume 30, Issue 2, pp 149–154. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s12110-019-09342-8
Abstract: The Seville Statement on Violence rejected the view that violence and war were in any way rooted in human nature and proclaimed that they were merely a cultural artifact. This paper points out both the valid and invalid parts of the statement. It concludes that the potential for both war and peace is embedded in us. The human behavioral toolkit comprises a number of major tools, respectively geared for violent conflict, peaceful competition, or cooperation, depending on people’s assessment of what will serve them best in any given circumstance. Conflict is only one tool—the hammer—in our diverse behavioral toolkit. However, all three behavioral strategies are not purely learned cultural forms. This naive nature/nurture dichotomy overlooks the heavy and complex biological machinery that is necessary for the working of each of them and the interplay between them. They are all very close under our skin and readily activated because they have all been very handy during our long evolutionary past. At the same time, they are variably calibrated to particular conditions through social learning, which means that their relative use may fluctuate widely. Thus, state authority has tilted the menu of human choices in the direction of the peaceful options in the domestic arena, and changing economic, social, and political conditions may be generating a similar effect in the international arena.
Check also The phylogenetic roots of human lethal violence. José María Gómez et al. Nature volume 538, pages 233–237 (October 13 2016). https://www.bipartisanalliance.com/2018/02/the-phylogenetic-roots-of-human-lethal.html
---
Seville Statement on Violence https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Seville_Statement_on_Violence
---
[The Seville statement] was published during the heyday of Rousseauism, the view that the
aboriginal human past, before the advent of agriculture and the state, was nonviolent
and peaceful. This view dominated anthropology and culture in general during that time
and was itself a reaction against earlier scholarly theories and popular books, such as
those by Ardrey (1966), Lorenz (1966), and Morris (1967), which presented war as
unique to humans, a primary drive rooted in human nature and erupting irresistibly.
Thus, the statement rejected the view that violence and war were in any way rooted in
human nature and proclaimed that they were merely a cultural artifact.
In the context of the reaction against Rousseauism, the Seville Statement has been
criticized as an example of false-consciousness and the subordination of scholarly
integrity to an ideological cause, noble as it may be (e.g., Beroldi 1994; Manson and
Wrangham 1987; Pinker 1997). While this criticism is fully justified, I take this
opportunity to point out both the valid and invalid parts of the statement. In doing
so, I hope to clarify why people actually fight; whether fighting is in human nature, and
in what sense; and, consequently, whether violence and war can be eliminated or, more
realistically, drastically reduced.
Because the biological underpinning of war and peace has been the subject of much
confusion and a heated controversy—among neurobiologists, ethologists, anthropologists,
psychologists, political scientists and others—it is in great need of clarification. And the
root of the confusion is this: People habitually assume that if widespread deadly violence
has always been with us, it must be a primary, “irresistible” biological drive that is nearly
impossible to suppress. Many find in this conclusion sufficient reason to object to the idea
that human fighting is as old as our species, whereas others regard it as compelling evidence
that war is inevitable.2 However, both sides are wrong. Contrary to fashionable 1960s
notions, traced back to Freud’s latter-day theorizing about a death drive or instinct, thanatos
(Freud 1920, 1923, 1930, 1933a, b), violence is not a primary drive that requires release,
like hunger or sex. The Swiss or Swedes, for example, who have not fought another
country for two centuries, show no special signs of deprivation on this account. But try to
deny them food for more than a few hours, or sex, say, for more than a few days, and see
what will happen. [...]
On the other hand, the fact that violence is not a primary drive does not mean that we
are not hardwired for it. Studies on “warless” pre-state societies usually intend to prove
that warfare, being neither primordial nor natural to humankind, was probably a late,
and in any case wholly contingent, cultural phenomenon. Margaret Mead’s framing of the problem: “Warfare Is Only an Invention – Not a Biological Necessity” (1940), is the
mother of all mistakes. It expresses the widespread assumption that violence must be
either a primary drive or entirely learned, whereas in reality, its potential is deeply
ingrained in us as a means or tool, ever ready to be employed. People can cooperate,
compete peacefully, or use violence to achieve their objectives, depending on what
they believe will serve them best in any given circumstance. In cooperation, the parties
combine efforts, in principle because the synergic outcome of their efforts divided
among them promises greater benefit to each of them than their independent efforts
might. In competition, each party strives to outdo the other in order to achieve a desired
good by employing whatever means they have at their disposal except direct action
against the other. Competition runs parallel. By contrast, in a conflict, direct action
against the competitor is taken in order to eliminate it or lessen its ability to engage in
the competition (Simmel 1955).
Cooperation, competition, and conflict are the three fundamental forms of social
interaction (in addition to avoidance, or zero interaction). People have always had all
three options to choose from, and they have always assessed the situation to decide
which option, or combination of them, seemed the most promising. Indeed, hunter-gatherer societies have elaborate procedures of conflict resolution, especially within
their groups, precisely because conflict, often violent, is an ever-present and often
occurring threat. People are well equipped biologically for pursuing any of the above
behavioral strategies, with conflict being only one tool, albeit a major one—the
hammer—in our diverse behavioral toolkit. Furthermore, Homo sapiens is a social
species, whose local and regional groups—universally and uniquely bound together by
ties of both kinship and shared cultural codes, including language and customs—
cooperate within themselves in a variety of group activities, including fighting. Group
fighting is often pursued for the attainment of collective goods, above all hunting
territory and other scarce sources of food, as well as reproduction opportunities.
Thus, neither a late invention nor a compulsive inevitability independent of conditions,
group fighting is part of our evolution-shaped behavioral menu. It is in this sense that both
war and peace are “in our genes,” which accounts for their widely fluctuating prevalence in
different sociohistorical contexts. The Seville Statement rightly puts it, in rejection of the
view that human biology makes violence and war inescapable: “There is nothing in our
neurophysiology that compels us to react violently. . . . We conclude that biology does not
condemn humanity to war.” However, the statement fell into the opposite fallacy,
proclaiming that warfare “is a product of culture” and solemnly prescribing that “IT IS
SCIENTIFICALLY INCORRECT [emphasis in the original] to say that war or any other
violent behavior is genetically programmed into our human nature.” The statement carelessly concluded: “Violence is neither in our evolutionary legacy nor in our genes.”
In reality, the potential for both war and peace is imbedded in us. Although activated
interchangeably and conjointly in response to the overall environmental and sociocultural conditions, all three behavioral strategies—violent conflict, peaceful competition,
and cooperation—are not purely learned cultural forms. This naive nature/nurture
dichotomy overlooks the heavy and complex biological machinery that is necessary
for the working of each of these behavioral strategies and the interplay between them.
Certainly, these deep, evolution-shaped patterns are variably calibrated to particular
conditions through social learning. However, the reason why they are all there, very
close under our skin and readily activated, is that they were all very handy during our long evolutionary history. They all proved highly useful and advantageous, thereby
becoming part and parcel of our biological equipment.
A number of scholars who have dealt with the question in fact express the view that
human societies have always been Janus-faced, interchangeably resorting to both peace
and violent conflict. According to Walker (2001:590): “Everywhere we probe into the
history of our species we find evidence of a similar pattern of behavior: People have
always been capable of both kindness and extreme cruelty.” Burch (2005),
documenting the Alaskan Eskimos’ highly belligerent record, also devotes one part
of his book to their peaceful interactions. Robert Kelly (2013:158, 165) writes: “To
summarize so far, it is not useful to ask whether hunter-gatherers (inclusive of egalitarian and nonegalitarian types) are peaceful or warlike: we find evidence for both
among them.” He adds: “Aggression appears in many species, suggesting that it has a
long evolutionary history. . . . It is part of our behavioral repertoire, and at times served
us well.”
Boehm (2013:333) similarly rejects the view “that there should be an either-or
choice between setting up friendly, cooperative relations with neighbors, as opposed to
fighting with them.” Both took place, interchangeably, with the same and with different
neighbors. Based on his survey of 49 simple hunter-gatherer societies, Boehm
(2013:334, also 327, 333) writes: “The finding here is that intergroup conflict and
external peacekeeping would both seem to have been prominent in human political life,
back to at least 45,000 BP and probably earlier.”
Boehm (2013:327) puts both sides of simple hunter-gatherer societies’ behavioral
repertoire in a proper perspective: “59 percent of the . . . forager sample has enough
lethal intergroup conflict for this to be reported in an ethnography.” He adds
(2013:330): “With human foragers, negotiations of some type (including truces and
peacemaking) are found in more than half of the . . . societies surveyed (59 percent).
However . . . formal and effective peacemaking is reported only for a few of the 29
societies.”
3 Hunter-gatherers suffered far greater violent mortality rates than state
societies not because they lacked well-established and partly successful patterns of
conflict resolution. It is just that hunter-gatherers’ anarchic condition, the absence of
effective coercive authority, limited the effectiveness of these patterns as compared to
state societies.
Wars have been fought for the attainment of the same objects of human desire that
underlie the human motivational system in general—only by violent means, through the
use of force. Here I take issue with Pinker’s excellent The Better Angels of Our Nature
(2011), with whom I am otherwise in much agreement. “Angels” versus “Demons” in
the human behavioral system is an allusion to Lincoln’s first inaugural address and is
largely invoked metaphorically. And yet not entirely, because Pinker points to particular
human quests such as dominance or ideology as “demons” with which the blame for
war rests. Yet, dominance or ideology, no less than the desire for sex, can just as well be
counted on the side of the “angels”—when pursued by peaceful means and for peaceful
ends. For example, there have always been peaceful ideologies—such as Buddhism,
and, in principle, though all too often not in practice, Christianity—which have
exercised a considerable pacifying effect.
Furthermore, the distinctions that Pinker draws between different categories of
violence respectively related to the above “demons” are also questionable. He cites studies showing that separate parts of the brain may trigger violent behavior, which is
true of nearly all behaviors. But this does not mean that all violent behaviors are not
subject to, and regulated by, a unified evolutionary calculus originally designed to
advance survival and reproduction, the very definition of the evolutionary rationale
which Pinker as an evolutionist would surely be the first to accept.
The “problem” of war is not these or other human desires. Rather, violence and war
occur when the conflictual behavioral strategy is judged to be more promising than
peaceful competition and cooperation for achieving scarce objects of human desire.
Both our basic desires and the conditions that channel the efforts to fulfil them to the
conflictual path are necessary for understanding why war occurs.
Thus, the advent of coercive state authority and state policing has tilted the menu of
the human behavioral strategies in the direction of the peaceful options in the domestic
arena, affecting a great reduction in the rate of killings—in the form of homicide and
blood revenge—within societies. Moreover, changing economic, social, and political
conditions have been generating a similar effect in the international arena, most notably
where a modern liberal economic and political order prevails and peaceful behavioral
options become that much more rewarding than the violent option in achieving
unprecedented levels of affluence and comfort (Gat 2006, 2017; Goldstein 2011;
Morris 2014; Pinker 2011). It is not that modern war has become more costly compared
with earlier times, as many believe—it has not; it is peace that has become more
rewarding (Gat 2006, 2017). Thus, countries with (non-oil) GDP per capita higher than
$20,000 no longer fight each other, nor experience civil war. The most developed parts
of the world, such as Western Europe and North America, have become a zone of
peace. Within them war is not even contemplated, or feared—the famous “Security
Dilemma” has disappeared—a situation which is unparalleled in history. [...]
Tuesday, December 31, 2019
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment