The
end of history. Hanno Sauer. Inquiry, Sep 19 2022.
https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2022.2124542
Abstract:
What credence should we assign to philosophical claims that were
formed without any knowledge of the current state of the art of the
philosophical debate and little or no knowledge of the relevant
empirical or scientific data? Very little or none. Yet when we engage
with the history of philosophy, this is often exactly what we do
[sic, it means, to give credence]. In this paper, I argue that
studying the history of philosophy is philosophically unhelpful. The
epistemic aims of philosophy, if there are any, are frustrated by
engaging with the history of philosophy, because we have little
reason to think that the claims made by history’s great
philosophers would survive closer scrutiny today. First, I review the
case for philosophical historiography and show how it falls short. I
then present several arguments for skepticism about the philosophical
value of engaging with the history of philosophy and offer an
explanation for why philosophical historiography would seem to make
sense even if it didn’t.
Keywords:
History of philosophymetaphilosophyphilosophical methodologysocial
epistemologyepistemic peerhood
Consider Plato’s or Rousseau’s evaluation of the virtues and vices of democracy. Here is a (non-exhaustive) list of evidence and theories that were unavailable to them at the time:
Historical experiences with developed democracies
Empirical evidence regarding democratic movements in developing countries
Various formal theorems regarding collective decision making and preference aggregation, such as the Condorcet Jury-Theorem, Arrow’s Impossibility-Results, the Hong-Page-Theorem, the median voter theorem, the miracle of aggregation, etc.
Existing studies on voter behavior, polarization, deliberation, information
Public choice economics, incl. rational irrationality, democratic realism
The whole subsequent debate on their own arguments
[…]
When it comes to people currently alive, we would steeply discount the merits of the contribution of any philosopher whose work were utterly uninformed by the concepts, theories and evidence just mentioned (and whatever other items belong on this list). It is not clear why the great philosophers of the past should not be subjected to the same standard. (Bear in mind that time and attention are severely limited resources. Therefore, every decision we make about whose work to dedicate our time and attention to faces important trade-offs.)
The nature/nurture debate in moral psychology illustrates the same point. Philosophers have long discussed whether there is an innate moral faculty, and what its content may consist in. Now consider which theories and evidence were unavailable to historical authors such as Hume or Kant when they developed their views on the topic, and compare this to a recent contribution to the debate (Nichols et al. 2016):
Linguistic corpus data
Evolutionary psychology
Universal moral grammar theory
Sophisticated statistical methods
Bayesian formal modeling
250 years of the nature/nurture debate
250 years of subsequent debates on Hume or Kant
[…]
Finally, consider Hobbes’ justification of political authority in terms of how it allows us to avoid the unpleasantness of the state of nature. Here are some concepts and theories that were not available to him when he devised his arguments:
Utility functions
Nash equilibria
Dominant strategy
Backward induction
Behavioral economics
Experimental game theory
Biological evidence on the adaptivity of cooperation
Empirical evidence regarding life in hunter/gatherer societies
Cross-cultural data regarding life in contemporary tribal societies
[…]
Again, when it comes to deciding whose philosophical work to devote our time and attention to, any person that didn’t have any knowledge whatsoever of the above items would be a dubious choice.
A version of this problem that is somewhat more specific to moral philosophy is that in ethics, it is often important not to assign disproportionate testimonial weight to people of which we have good reasons to suspect that they harbored deeply objectionable attitudes or publicly expressed moral beliefs we have reason to deem unjustified and/or morally odious. Personally, I have made a habit of not heeding the ethical advice of Adolf Eichmann, Ted Bundy, and various of my family members. But upon looking at the moral views held by many of the most prominent authors in the history of philosophy, one often cannot help but shudder: Plato advocated abolishing the family, violently if need be; Aristotle defended (a version of) slavery as natural; Locke advocated religious toleration, only to exclude atheists from the social contract; Kant argued that masturbation is one of the gravest moral transgressions there is; Hegel claimed that it is an a priori truth that the death penalty is morally obligatory, and indeed a form of respect towards the executed; the list of historical philosophers who held sexist, racist and other discriminatory views would be too long to recount here.